Wir haben Thing Frankfurt 2010 auf eine neue Seite umgestellt. http://www.thing-frankfurt.de
Dies ist nun die alte Seite. Als Archiv 2003 - 2010.
Ihre Adresse lautet http://last.thing-frankfurt.de
Thing Frankfurt - Kunst, Kritik, neue Medien ausserhalb von Galerien und Institutionen seit 1992 Banner: multi.trudi artspace - a partner of Thing Frankfurt
New here?

Kunst, Kritik und neue Medien / Art, critique, new media Search | Sitemap | Imprint & Datenschutz | Contact 
General Info
Frankfurt Art
Locator
Media
Search
Donate
Text Department- online writing texts and mechanisms

The Infinite Art Process, 1/12/96

alone been able to show is that, then, the pure employment of our sense receptions is the key to understanding our sense receptions, yet the paralogisms can not take account of, in the case of our art experience, reason.

By means of sabotage, the Antinomies of Art exclude the possibility of the employment of the Art-Space, yet the transcendental unity of reception is just as necessary as, even as this relates to the Art-Time, philosophy of art. We can deduce that metaphysics of art, by means of Media Art, would be falsified. I assert that our sense receptions (and there can be no doubt that this is the case) would thereby be made to contradict the Categories of Art.

It is obvious that Media Art (and what we have alone been able to show is that this is true) teaches us nothing whatsoever regarding the content of the artwork in itself. Dan Cameron tells us that the Museum is the mere result of the power of a painting, a blind but indispensable function of the soul.

It is not at all certain that, in particular, transcendental logic teaches us nothing whatsoever regarding the content of a painting, but our a priori knowledge is just as necessary as the architectonic of human reason. What we have alone been able to show is that our sense receptions prove the validity of the Transcendental Deduction of Art.

In all theoretical sciences of Art, natural reason is the clue to the discovery of, even as this relates to the transcendental aesthetic, the Transcendental Deduction of Art. What we have alone been able to show is that our judgements, in accordance with the principles of the Categories of Art, occupy part of the sphere of the ideal Artwork concerning the existence of natural causes of Art in general.

Thus, the artwork in itself stands in need of, in other words, the ideal Artwork. By means of nuclear fusion, our concepts (and let us suppose that this is the case) have nothing to do with our sense receptions. As we have already seen, what we have alone been able to show is that, in reference to ends, the Transcendental Deduction of Art proves the validity of the Art-Space, but our ideas of Art, on the other hand, have lying before them Media Art.

Our deductive judgements would thereby be made to contradict, so far as I know, our judgements. This often happens when you prefer a piece of Art over a beautiful women. As we have already seen, our concepts (and Adorno reminds us that this is the case) would thereby be made to contradict the artworks in space and time. To avoid all misapprehension, it is necessary to explain that, then, our a priori concepts, so regarded, abstract from all content of knowledge, and formal logic, still, exists in natural causes of Art.

The reader should be careful to observe that the infinite Art-Process stands in need of, certainly, the noumena of Art. (It remains a mystery why, even as this relates to the Art-Time, the phenomena of Art stand in need to, when thus treated as our faculties, the Categories of Art, but our judgements exclude the possibility of the artworks in themselves.)

As is evident upon close examination, what we have alone been able to show is that natural causes of Art are just as necessary as, so regarded, the Categories of Art; thus, natural causes of Art are the clue to the discovery of, for these reasons, the transcendental aesthetic. What we have alone been able to show is that the transcendental unity of reception is the key to understanding our a posteriori concepts. The Antinomies of Art have lying before them the Gallery.

To avoid all misapprehension, it is necessary to explain that the Antinomies of Art have nothing to do with, however, our understanding of art, because of our necessary ignorance of the conditions. As is proven in the ontological manuals, the artworks in space and time (and Kasper König tells us that this is the case) are a representation of the manifold of Art Pieces. (Consequently, the noumena of Art are just as necessary as the Artworks in space and time, by means of analytic unity.)

Because of the relation between the transcendental unity of reception and the paralogisms, there can be no doubt that the Museum is the mere result of the power of the Gallery, a blind but indispensable function of the soul; certainly, the discipline of beautiful reason, in reference to ends, teaches us nothing whatsoever regarding the content of our understanding of art. It must not be supposed that, indeed, our faculties, in the study of the ideal Artwork, stand in need to the Ideal of cynical reason.

But to this matter no answer is possible. The transcendental Artworks in space and time are just as necessary as the ideal Artwork, because of the relation between the Art-Time and the Antinomies of Art. The Antinomies of Art have nothing to do with, on the contrary, the Artworks in space and time, by means of analytic unity. In all theoretical sciences of Art, our disjunctive judgements have lying before them the Ideal of practical reason, as any dedicated reader can clearly see.

In natural art, let us suppose that the Art-Space occupies part of the sphere of the Art-Space concerning the existence of the empirical Artworks in space and time in general. The Categories of Art, thus, are the clue to the discovery of our ideas of Art. As we have already seen, the architectonic of pure reason occupies part of the sphere of necessity concerning the existence of our judgements in general, and our faculties have lying before them our ideas of Art. By means of nuclear fission, it must not be supposed that the paralogisms (and Walter Benjamin tells us that this is the case) have lying before them the paralogisms of natural Art.

As I have elsewhere shown, the phenomena of Art would be falsified. By means of analysis, a painting is the key to understanding the Antinomies of Art, but the artworks in space and time have nothing to do with, in so far as this expounds the universal rules of the transcendental aesthetic, our concepts.

The reader should be careful to observe that, in other words, philosophy of art, however, is by its very nature contradictory, but the transcendental Artworks in space and time, in view of these considerations, can never, as a whole, furnish a true and demonstrated science, because, like philosophy of art, they can not take account of inductive principles. It is not at all certain that our faculties, in the case of philosophy of art, constitute a body of demonstrated doctrine, and some of this body must be known a priori.

As is proven in the ontological manuals, Adorno reminds us that, in reference to ends, necessity, in the case of our art experience, is by its very nature contradictory.

Kasper König tells us that the artworks in space and time can not take account of modern Sexuality. And similarly with all the others.

The Museum excludes the possibility of the transcendental aesthetic. Because of the relation between our a posteriori knowledge and our judgements, the Categories of Art are a representation of the Art-Space.

By virtue of beautiful reason, the paralogisms of practical Art, in the case of the transcendental aesthetic, constitute the whole content for the transcendental aesthetic. The reader should be careful to observe that the artworks in space and time (and let us suppose that this is the case) can not take account of the artworks in themselves; for these reasons, transcendental logic (and the reader should be careful to observe that this is true) has lying before it the noumena of Art. Is it the case that our art experience has nothing to do with the transcendental unity of reception, or is the real question whether natural causes of Art are the mere results of the power of the Art-Time, a blind but indispensable function of the soul? It is obvious that the Gallery is the key to understanding Media Art.

Walter Benjamin reminds us that the ideal of human reason teaches us nothing whatsoever regarding the content of philosophy of art. It is obvious that our a posteriori concepts prove the validity of, for example, Picasso; as I have elsewhere shown, the Artworks in space and time are the clue to the discovery of the Antinomies of Art. Let us suppose that, so far as regards our art experience and the artworks in themselves, our ideas of Art exclude the possibility of, on the other hand, the paralogisms, yet the Antinomies of Art exclude the possibility of, in so far as this expounds the contradictory rules of our concepts, the architectonic of natural reason.

On the other hand, the Antinomies of Art, for these reasons, occupy part of the sphere of the discipline of practical reason concerning the existence of the Antinomies of Art in general. It is obvious that natural causes of Art, that is to say, occupy part of the sphere of philosophy of art concerning the existence of our sense receptions in general; in the study of the Gallery, the Art-Time (and it is not at all certain that this is true) is a representation of our a posteriori knowledge. It is not at all certain that the discipline of natural reason may not contradict itself, but it is still possible that it may be in contradiction with modern Sexuality. It must not be supposed that the architectonic of natural reason has lying before it, so far as I know, the Art-Time.

Let us suppose that our sense receptions are a representation of the ideal Artwork; in view of these considerations, the discipline of pure reason, in respect of the intelligible character, can be treated like the noumena of Art. #

However, the discipline of natural reason would be falsified. There can be no doubt that the transcendental Artworks in space and time, certainly, would be falsified; thus, the artworks in themselves are just as necessary as the transcendental aesthetic. Our concepts, however, exist in Media Art, since knowledge of our a posteriori concepts is a posteriori. As will easily be shown in the next section, Picasso stands in need of, consequently, our concepts.

By means of analytic unity, the artworks in space and time are the mere results of the power of the Art-Space, a blind but indispensable function of the soul; in the case of necessity, the practical employment of the ideal Artwork can never furnish a true and demonstrated science, because, like our art experience, it would thereby be made to contradict speculative principles.

Since all the same of our sense receptions are disjunctive, the artworks in themselves have lying before them the Art-Space, yet our sense receptions can not take account of the ideal Artwork. By means of nuclear fission, to avoid all misapprehension, it is necessary to explain that natural causes of Art are a representation of our concepts.

As we have already seen, it remains a mystery why sarcastical reason, in particular, can never furnish a true and demonstrated science, because, like the never-ending regress in the series of empirical art conditions, it is what first gives rise to inductive principles. The reader should be careful to observe that our faculties, in accordance with the principles of reason, constitute a body of demonstrated doctrine, and some of this body must be known a priori; in all theoretical sciences of Art, our sense receptions, so far as regards the transcendental aesthetic, would be falsified. It must not be supposed that our faculties, in all theoretical sciences of Art, would be falsified. I feel I have sufficiently shown this to be true.

As is proven in the ontological manuals, the reader should be careful to observe that the architectonic of natural reason has nothing to do with necessity; in all theoretical sciences of Art, natural causes of Art are the mere results of the power of the discipline of beautiful reason, a blind but indispensable function of the soul.

Since knowledge of our faculties is a posteriori, our sense receptions stand in need to the architectonic of practical reason. Since some of natural causes of Art are ampliative, we can deduce that, on the contrary, the phenomena of Art are just as necessary as the Gallery.

The Artworks in space and time abstract from all content of knowledge, and the infinite Art-Process, in respect of its intelligible character, is the mere result of the power of the ideal Artwork, a blind but indispensable function of the soul. By means of nuclear fission, the artwork in itself may not contradict itself, but it is still possible that it may be in contradiction with necessity, and human reason proves the validity of general logic.

It remains a mystery why, so far as I know, Media Art is the key to understanding our ideas of Art, but our a posteriori concepts exclude the possibility of human reason. Because of our necessary ignorance of the conditions, the architectonic of pure reason, insomuch as applied logic relies on the noumena of Art, occupies part of the sphere of the infinite Art-Process concerning the existence of our judgements in general, yet the ideal Artwork occupies part of the sphere of Media Art concerning the existence of our concepts in general.

We can deduce that, for example, the Art-Space is a representation of the Categories of Art. In all theoretical sciences of Art, our faculties, so regarded, can be treated like metaphysics of art, as any dedicated reader can clearly see.

The reader should be careful to observe that, so far as I know, the empirical Artworks in space and time, consequently, can never, as a whole, furnish a true and demonstrated science. What we have alone been able to show is that, then, the pure employment of our sense receptions is the key to understanding our sense receptions, yet the paralogisms can not take account of, in the case of our art experience, reason.

By means of sabotage, the Antinomies of Art exclude the possibility of the employment of the Art-Space, yet the transcendental unity of reception is just as necessary as, even as this relates to the Art-Time, philosophy of art.

We can deduce that metaphysics of art, by means of Media Art, would be falsified. I assert that our sense receptions (and there can be no doubt that this is the case) would thereby be made to contradict the Categories of Art. It is obvious that Media Art (and what we have alone been able to show is that this is true) teaches us nothing whatsoever regarding the content of the artwork in itself.

Dan Cameron tells us that the Museum is the mere result of the power of a painting, a blind but indispensable function of the soul. It is not at all certain that, in particular, transcendental logic teaches us nothing whatsoever regarding the content of a painting, but our a priori knowledge is just as necessary as the architectonic of human reason.

What we have alone been able to show is that our sense receptions prove the validity of the Transcendental Deduction of Art. In all theoretical sciences of Art, natural reason is the clue to the discovery of, even as this relates to the transcendental aesthetic, the Transcendental Deduction of Art. What we have alone been able to show is that our judgements, in accordance with the principles of the Categories of Art, occupy part of the sphere of the ideal Artwork concerning the existence of natural causes of Art in general.

Thus, the artwork in itself stands in need of, in other words, the ideal Artwork. By means of nuclear fusion, our concepts (and let us suppose that this is the case) have nothing to do with our sense receptions. As we have already seen, what we have alone been able to show is that, in reference to ends, the Transcendental Deduction of Art proves the validity of the Art-Space, but our ideas of Art, on the other hand, have lying before them Media Art. Our deductive judgements would thereby be made to contradict, so far as I know, our judgements.

This often happens when you prefer a piece of Art over a beautiful women.

As we have already seen, our concepts (and Adorno reminds us that this is the case) would thereby be made to contradict the artworks in space and time.

To avoid all misapprehension, it is necessary to explain that, then, our a priori concepts, so regarded, abstract from all content of knowledge, and formal logic, still, exists in natural causes of Art. The reader should be careful to observe that the infinite Art-Process stands in need of, certainly, the noumena of Art. (It remains a mystery why, even as this relates to the Art-Time, the phenomena of Art stand in need to, when thus treated as our faculties, the Categories of Art, but our judgements exclude the possibility of the artworks in themselves.)

As is evident upon close examination, what we have alone been able to show is that natural causes of Art are just as necessary as, so regarded, the Categories of Art; thus, natural causes of Art are the clue to the discovery of, for these reasons, the transcendental aesthetic. What we have alone been able to show is that the transcendental unity of reception is the key to understanding our a posteriori concepts.

The Antinomies of Art have lying before them the Gallery.

To avoid all misapprehension, it is necessary to explain that the Antinomies of Art have nothing to do with, however, our understanding of art, because of our necessary ignorance of the conditions.

As is proven in the ontological manuals, the artworks in space and time (and Kasper König tells us that this is the case) are a representation of the manifold of Art Pieces. (Consequently, the noumena of Art are just as necessary as the Artworks in space and time, by means of analytic unity.) Because of the relation between the transcendental unity of reception and the paralogisms, there can be no doubt that the Museum is the mere result of the power of the Gallery, a blind but indispensable function of the soul; certainly, the discipline of beautiful reason, in reference to ends, teaches us nothing whatsoever regarding the content of our understanding of art.

It must not be supposed that, indeed, our faculties, in the study of the ideal Artwork, stand in need to the Ideal of cynical reason. But to this matter no answer is possible. The transcendental Artworks in space and time are just as necessary as the ideal Artwork, because of the relation between the Art-Time and the Antinomies of Art. The Antinomies of Art have nothing to do with, on the contrary, the Artworks in space and time, by means of analytic unity. In all theoretical sciences of Art, our disjunctive judgements have lying before them the Ideal of practical reason, as any dedicated reader can clearly see. In natural art, let us suppose that the Art-Space occupies part of the sphere of the Art-Space concerning the existence of the empirical Artworks in space and time in general. The Categories of Art, thus, are the clue to the discovery of our ideas of Art. As we have already seen, the architectonic of pure reason occupies part of the sphere of necessity concerning the existence of our judgements in general, and our faculties have lying before them our ideas of Art. By means of nuclear fission, it must not be supposed that the paralogisms (and Walter Benjamin tells us that this is the case) have lying before them the paralogisms of natural Art. As I have elsewhere shown, the phenomena of Art would be falsified. By means of analysis, a painting is the key to understanding the Antinomies of Art, but the artworks in space and time have nothing to do with, in so far as this expounds the universal rules of the transcendental aesthetic, our concepts. The reader should be careful to observe that, in other words, philosophy of art, however, is by its very nature contradictory, but the transcendental Artworks in space and time, in view of these considerations, can never, as a whole, furnish a true and demonstrated science, because, like philosophy of art, they can not take account of inductive principles. It is not at all certain that our faculties, in the case of philosophy of art, constitute a body of demonstrated doctrine, and some of this body must be known a priori. As is proven in the ontological manuals, Adorno reminds us that, in reference to ends, necessity, in the case of our art experience, is by its very nature contradictory.

Kasper König tells us that the artworks in space and time can not take account of modern Sexuality. And similarly with all the others.

The Museum excludes the possibility of the transcendental aesthetic. Because of the relation between our a posteriori knowledge and our judgements, the Categories of Art are a representation of the Art-Space. By virtue of beautiful reason, the paralogisms of practical Art, in the case of the transcendental aesthetic, constitute the whole content for the transcendental aesthetic.

The reader should be careful to observe that the artworks in space and time (and let us suppose that this is the case) can not take account of the artworks in themselves; for these reasons, transcendental logic (and the reader should be careful to observe that this is true) has lying before it the noumena of Art. Is it the case that our art experience has nothing to do with the transcendental unity of reception, or is the real question whether natural causes of Art are the mere results of the power of the Art-Time, a blind but indispensable function of the soul?

It is obvious that the Gallery is the key to understanding Media Art.

Walter Benjamin reminds us that the Ideal of human reason teaches us nothing whatsoever regarding the content of philosophy of art. It is obvious that our a posteriori concepts prove the validity of, for example, Picasso; as I have elsewhere shown, the Artworks in space and time are the clue to the discovery of the Antinomies of Art.

Let us suppose that, so far as regards our art experience and the artworks in themselves, our ideas of Art exclude the possibility of, on the other hand, the paralogisms, yet the Antinomies of Art exclude the possibility of, in so far as this expounds the contradictory rules of our concepts, the architectonic of natural reason. On the other hand, the Antinomies of Art, for these reasons, occupy part of the sphere of the discipline of practical reason concerning the existence of the Antinomies of Art in general.

It is obvious that natural causes of Art, that is to say, occupy part of the sphere of philosophy of art concerning the existence of our sense receptions in general; in the study of the Gallery, the Art-Time (and it is not at all certain that this is true) is a representation of our a posteriori knowledge. It is not at all certain that the discipline of natural reason may not contradict itself, but it is still possible that it may be in contradiction with modern Sexuality.

It must not be supposed that the architectonic of natural reason has lying before it, so far as I know, the Art-Time. Let us suppose that our sense receptions are a representation of the ideal Artwork; in view of these considerations, the discipline of pure reason, in respect of the intelligible character, can be treated like the noumena of Art. However, the discipline of natural reason would be falsified. There can be no doubt that the transcendental Artworks in space and time, certainly, would be falsified; thus, the artworks in themselves are just as necessary as the transcendental aesthetic.

Our concepts, however, exist in Media Art, since knowledge of our a posteriori concepts is a posteriori.

As will easily be shown in the next section, Picasso stands in need of, consequently, our concepts. By means of analytic unity, the artworks in space and time are the mere results of the power of the Art-Space, a blind but indispensable function of the soul; in the case of necessity, the practical employment of the ideal Artwork can never furnish a true and demonstrated science, because, like our art experience, it would thereby be made to contradict speculative principles.

Since all the same of our sense receptions are disjunctive, the artworks in themselves have lying before them the Art-Space, yet our sense receptions can not take account of the ideal Artwork. By means of nuclear fission, to avoid all misapprehension, it is necessary to explain that natural causes of Art are a representation of our concepts.

As we have already seen, it remains a mystery why sarcastical reason, in particular, can never furnish a true and demonstrated science, because, like the never-ending regress in the series of empirical art conditions, it is what first gives rise to inductive principles. The reader should be careful to observe that our faculties, in accordance with the principles of reason, constitute a body of demonstrated doctrine, and some of this body must be known a priori; in all theoretical sciences of Art, our sense receptions, so far as regards the transcendental aesthetic, would be falsified.

It must not be supposed that our faculties, in all theoretical sciences of Art, would be falsified. I feel I have sufficiently shown this to be true. As is proven in the ontological manuals, the reader should be careful to observe that the architectonic of natural reason has nothing to do with necessity; in all theoretical sciences of Art, natural causes of Art are the mere results of the power of the discipline of beautiful reason, a blind but indispensable function of the soul. Since knowledge of our faculties is a posteriori, our sense receptions stand in need to the architectonic of practical reason. Since some of natural causes of Art are ampliative, we can deduce that, on the contrary, the phenomena of Art are just as necessary as the Gallery.

The Artworks in space and time abstract from all content of knowledge, and the infinite Art-Process, in respect of the intelligible character, is the mere result of the power of the ideal Artwork, a blind but indispensable function of the soul. By means of nuclear fission, the artwork in itself may not contradict itself, but it is still possible that it may be in contradiction with necessity, and human reason proves the validity of general logic.

It remains a mystery why, so far as I know, Media Art is the key to understanding our ideas of Art, but our a posteriori concepts exclude the possibility of human reason. Because of our necessary ignorance of the conditions, the architectonic of pure reason, insomuch as applied logic relies on the noumena of Art, occupies part of the sphere of the infinite Art-Process concerning the existence of our judgements in general, yet the ideal Artwork occupies part of the sphere of Media Art concerning the existence of our concepts in general.

We can deduce that, for example, the Art-Space is a representation of the Categories of Art. In all theoretical sciences of Art, our faculties, so regarded, can be treated like metaphysics of art, as any dedicated reader can clearly see.

The reader should be careful to observe that, so far as I know, the empirical Artworks in space and time, consequently, can never, as a whole, furnish a true and demonstrated science, because, like Picasso, they have lying before them problematic principles, and modern Sexuality are the clue to the discovery of the artworks in themselves. By means of nuclear fusion, Picasso stands in need of, in view of these considerations, natural causes of Art; certainly, the artworks in space and time, for these reasons, abstract from all content of knowledge. (Our sense receptions, however, can be treated like the Ideal of beautiful reason, and the Categories of Art (and the reader should be careful to observe that this is the case) have lying before them our faculties.)

By means of sabotage, I assert that the ideal Artwork is the mere result of the power of formal logic, a blind but indispensable function of the soul; with the sole exception of the discipline of practical reason, our ideas of Art are the clue to the discovery of our ideas of Art. By means of analysis, the reader should be careful to observe that, then, the Antinomies of Art can be treated like modern Sexuality.

On this matter, what has been said already should in any case suffice by itself. Since knowledge of the Antinomies of Art is a posteriori, it must not be supposed that our ideas of Art would thereby be made to contradict, thus, the paralogisms; thus, Picasso is the mere result of the power of our understanding of art, a blind but indispensable function of the soul. Since knowledge of natural causes of Art is a priori, the ideal Artwork, indeed, is what first gives rise to our faculties.

Kasper König tells us that the noumena of Art, when thus treated as the Antinomies of Art, would be falsified. As we have already seen, the Art-Space can thereby determine in its totality the Categories of Art. (Since knowledge of the phenomena of Art is a posteriori, the Gallery can thereby determine in its totality the discipline of sarcastical reason.) By means of sabotage, our ideas of Art are a representation of, in the study of transcendental logic, the infinite Art-Process; by means of the ideal Artwork, our art experience, in the study of the Museum, abstracts from all content of knowledge. Natural causes of Art occupy part of the sphere of the discipline of pure reason concerning the existence of the artworks in space and time in general.

The divisions are thus provided; all that is required is to fill them. ore them problematic principles, and modern Sexuality are the clue to the discovery of the artworks in themselves. By means of nuclear fusion, Picasso stands in need of, in view of these considerations, natural causes of Art; certainly, the artworks in space and time, for these reasons, abstract from all content of knowledge. (Our sense receptions, however, can be treated like the Ideal of beautiful reason, and the Categories of Art (and the reader should be careful to observe that this is the case) have lying before them our faculties.)

By means of sabotage, I assert that the ideal Artwork is the mere result of the power of formal logic, a blind but indispensable function of the soul; with the sole exception of the discipline of practical reason, our ideas of Art are the clue to the discovery of our ideas of Art. By means of analysis, the reader should be careful to observe that, then, the Antinomies of Art can be treated like modern Sexuality.

On this matter, what has been said already should in any case suffice by itself. Since knowledge of the Antinomies of Art is a posteriori, it must not be supposed that our ideas of Art would thereby be made to contradict, thus, the paralogisms; thus, Picasso is the mere result of the power of our understanding of art, a blind but indispensable function of the soul. Since knowledge of natural causes of Art is a priori, the ideal Artwork, indeed, is what first gives rise to our faculties.

Kasper König tells us that the noumena of Art, when thus treated as the Antinomies of Art, would be falsified. As we have already seen, the Art-Space can thereby determine in its totality the Categories of Art. (Since knowledge of the phenomena of Art is a posteriori, the Gallery can thereby determine in its totality the discipline of sarcastical reason.) By means of sabotage, our ideas of Art are a representation of, in the study of transcendental logic, the infinite Art-Process; by means of the ideal Artwork, our art experience, in the study of the Museum, abstracts from all content of knowledge. Natural causes of Art occupy part of the sphere of the discipline of pure reason concerning the existence of the artworks in space and time in general. The divisions are

 

 

Comment on this page, or view other people's comments


© The Thing Frankfurt 1996

Acknowledgement:
This text was written with a modified version of Mark Pilgrims Kant Generator.

 

Anzeige

Become a member. Subscribe to: Mailingliste
Get the overview: Sitemap 
Find us on Twitter and Facebook
  • Save to del.icio.us
  • Thing Frankfurt is an example of netart.
  • Thing Frankfurt is a definition of netart.
  • Thing Frankfurt is more but netart.